A philosophic look at the Gnostic origins of 'transhumanism' and its intendant insanity, including gender fluidity and transgenderism.
From First Things
By Mark Shiffman
For ancient
philosophers, the dignity of contemplation lay in its fulfillment of our
longing for truth. The architects of modern thought championed analysis
for the sake of ever-greater power and security. The utopian island of
Francis Bacon’s New Atlantis features a massive research facility for natural sciences, dedicated to “the relief of man’s estate.” Galileo’s Dialogue Concerning Two New Sciences,
the foundational text of modern physics, begins with an inquiry into
the building of strong but buoyant warships, and ends with an analysis
of the parabolic motion of projectiles, which allows for highly accurate
artillery fire.
For the greatest salesman of this
utilitarian view of reason, Descartes, the goal of rigorous thought is
to “render ourselves the masters and possessors of nature.” Thus
empowered, we shall invent an “infinity of applications” which will not
only enable us to enjoy the goods of the earth without effort, but also
will free us from “an infinitude of maladies both of body and mind,”
thus securing “the preservation of health, which is without doubt the
chief blessing and the foundation of all other blessings in this life.”
He envisions these medical “applications” ultimately allowing us to
transcend the previous limits of our nature, freeing us from “the
infirmities of age,” and even “rendering men wiser and cleverer than
they have hitherto been.”
Today, the most ambitious Cartesian
dreams of life extension and enhancement set the agenda for
“transhumanism.” Although it styles itself a philosophy, transhumanism
is really a religious movement with a twenty-first-century marketing
campaign (under the brand “H+”). Like their prophet Descartes,
transhumanists think of the human being as a consciousness hosted in a
body, and of the body as a machine that the will can manipulate by means
of reason. Transhumanism adds a new technological claim: Computing
advances are on the verge of bringing about the “singularity,” a
convergence of artificial, computer-based intelligence and human,
brain-based intelligence. This convergence will allow us to transfer
ourselves out of the “wetware” of the brain and into super-sophisticated
hardware, thus enhancing our powers and possibly securing a kind of
immortality. We are on the brink of transcending the bodily limits that
have previously constrained humanity, thereby becoming transhuman.
It’s
easy to write transhumanism off as a fringe phenomenon of science
fantasy. But this is a mistake, for elements of it are already engulfing
us. A growing number of Americans now spend much of their time on the
Internet, living partly through machines and interacting with other
disembodied persons. Transgender therapies are increasingly common and
have widespread social and regulatory acceptance. Alongside its various
research initiatives to develop gadgets like self-driving cars, Google
has funded Calico, a research institute devoted to finding a cure for
aging, possibly through gene editing. Our technological pioneers are
already seeking and selling various ways to transcend the limitations of
our embodied humanity.
Among today’s prophets of transhumanism,
none has more mainstream clout than Steve Fuller. He holds a chair at
the University of Warwick fittingly named for Auguste Comte, the father
of sociology and proponent of the “religion of man.” Scholarly and
articulate, engaged and engaging, Fuller is the author of twenty-two
books (several of them lauded by mainstream periodicals), and a member
of the UK Academy of Social Sciences and the European Academy of
Sciences and Arts. He is probably the most effective spokesman and
advocate for practical policies that favor transhumanist research goals,
and has coined the catchiest label for the enhanced humanoids such a
research agenda aspires to produce: Humanity 2.0.
According to
Fuller, this agenda is driven by the same inspiration that is the source
of all religion. This is the human capacity for self-transcendence,
which he identifies as the foundation of our human dignity. Science
enables us to know dimensions of reality we will never experience with
our bodily senses, from the hidden world of cells to distant black
holes. It provides “an infinity of applications” that extend our powers
beyond the limits of the biologically given bodies of old-fashioned
Humanity 1.0. Science is thus the highest fulfillment of what makes us
human.
This vision of human dignity as technological
self-enhancement justifies the policy regime advocated in Fuller’s
recent book, coauthored with Veronika Lipinska, The Proactionary Imperative.
Max More coined the term “proactionary principle” in opposition to the
work of Leon Kass at the President’s Council on Bioethics, which argued
for a “precautionary principle” to prudently restrain experimentation
with the human genome. Fuller and Lipinska take up More’s coinage and
argue that innovation is necessary if we are to realize our distinctive
human capacity for self-transcendence; excessive caution does injustice
to our highest longings. We need to promote risk for the sake of
important advances in medical and other technologies that will benefit
us all, and compensate for their service those willing to take the
risks.
There is a compelling logic
to Fuller’s argument, if one accepts his premise about what constitutes
human dignity. He supports that premise, arguing that in fact we
generally do accept it, with a broad narrative of Western
intellectual-spiritual history. With provocative honesty, Fuller insists
that the core of this history is theological: Our zeal for scientific
self-transcendence is shaped by a widely shared modern vision of the
human relationship to the divine and to nature.
His story gets a
lot right, which is why it can seem so compelling. What it gets wrong,
however, helps us to see why his premise about self-transcendence is
untrue.
Drawing on some of the best work of theologian John
Milbank and his friends, Fuller identifies the Franciscan Duns Scotus as
a pivotal figure in the history of man’s self-image in the West.
Scotus’s importance hinges on a question of how we talk about God. While
the question seems highly technical, its cultural ramifications have
been immense.
In the generation before Scotus, Thomas Aquinas
argued that, although we have to use the same language to talk about
both creation and its Creator, the things we say can only be true
analogously in the two cases. When we say that God “knows” something,
“knowledge” cannot mean the same thing as it does when we speak of human
knowing, because the created order works within parameters given by the
Creator—parameters within which the Creator cannot be confined. At the
same time, the two meanings of “knowing” cannot be wholly unrelated,
because the creation is in some sense a reflection and manifestation of
God, its source. Our affirmations about God and created things, then,
are neither “equivocal” (using the same words very differently for
things in no way alike) nor “univocal” (using a word in the same sense
in both cases). The affirmation that God has goodness, wisdom, mercy,
justice, and even being can only be true by analogy, which combines
likeness and unlikeness.
Scotus
insists, on the contrary, that our affirmations are univocal. God and
humans have being in the same sense of the word. The difference is that
the being of humans (or any created thing) is finite, whereas God is the
infinite being. Fuller draws out the implications: “Divine attributes
differ from human ones only by degree not kind . . . . This in turn
allowed for direct comparisons between human and divine conditions of
being, and hence a trajectory of progress.” God possesses in infinite
degree all the excellences we possess in finite degree. This provides
later thinkers with the point of reference for our progressive
self-transcendence. We are aiming toward an ever-greater approximation
to God’s infinite perfection.
Though there are many links in the
chain, the theology of Scotus eventually leads to Feuerbach’s
progressive history of religion, according to which our successive ideas
of the divine are simply projections of human possibilities of
perfection onto a large screen that we call God. In early stages,
humanity conceived of human perfections as objects of worship and
aspiration, preparing the way for moderns like us to make them real in
our own lives, or at least to aspire to do so. This is the stream of
theology to which Comte, Nietzsche, and Mormon transhumanist Lincoln
Cannon belong: We become more godlike through our own efforts of
self-transcendence, rather than through humble prayer and petition and
self-giving love.
As Fuller notes, Scotus also gave a new sense
to the notion of “possibility.” In the older tradition, the possible is
what may happen within the order of creation, an order that reflects
God’s goodness. For Scotus, the world is the way it is only because that
is how God willed it to be. God could have willed to order creation in
an infinite number of other ways, since God’s will is unbounded and
arbitrary. The possible, then, includes all the things that might be or
might have been. The field of the possible is not only wider than
anything this particular created order permits, but wider than anything
we can even conceive.
This view of
possibility gives freedom an entirely different meaning. For the older
tradition, to be free is to be unimpeded from choosing the good, and all
created goods are participations in God’s goodness. Thus, love of what
is truly good is both liberating and fulfilling. It brings humans into
participation (analogously) in God’s own goodness. After Scotus, the
freedom of the will is its capacity to attach itself to any object
whatsoever, and to decide on an attachment is to limit freedom. Freedom
is willfulness (“voluntarism”). In this notion one can see the first
stirrings of the existentialist philosophy according to which humans
have no given nature, but define themselves by their decisions and
commitments.
The theology of Scotus exercised an enormous
influence on the nominalist theology and philosophy that swept through
the universities of the late Middle Ages. Nominalists share with Scotus
the voluntarist understanding of divine and human will, the
unboundedness of possibility, the view of creation as an order imposed
by God’s arbitrary will, and the rejection of the doctrine of analogy.
The nominalists concluded that our speech about God could only be
equivocal: As finite beings, we can have no concepts that capture the
infinite being of the infinitely transcendent God.
This
conclusion seems like humility in the face of God’s immensity. In fact,
however, its supposition that knowing means capturing things in concepts
provides the basis for the modern view of knowledge as power. For the
older tradition, knowing is participating receptively in the
intelligibility of things, an intelligibility that issues from the
divine intellect that ordered them and gave them their being and
natures. If possibility is unbounded, however, then knowing means
organizing experience by imposing orderly limits. Knowing the world
means organizing our concepts about it into a theoretical model that
somehow captures our experience. The ordered intelligibility of things
is constructed by us, not received from God through the medium of his
creation. This model-building approach underlies the view that the
scientific method is the only reliable way of knowing.
This
can all seem abstract and remote, but it shapes our cultural
assumptions in profound ways. It is remarkable how frequently, beginning
in the sixteenth century, we encounter in philosophical and literary
works the puzzle of how we can know we are awake and not dreaming.
Descartes expresses it with theological imagination: How do we know that
our conscious experience really reflects anything external to it,
rather than mere images produced in our mind by an omnipotent deceiver?
This deceiver is none other than the nominalist God, whose goodness is
no longer manifested to us by created beings, whose will is arbitrary,
and who confines our minds within one order out of the infinite range of
the possible. The same question of deception haunts popular culture in Twilight Zone episodes and (with a typical substitution of omnipotent A.I. for God) in The Matrix.
The training we receive in the scientific method and model construction
habituates us to making certain assumptions about who we are and how we
relate to nature. We are minds-producing-concepts for the purpose of
bringing the limitless possibilities of being into some order. These
assumptions, which have their origins in a theologically motivated
rejection of a classical understanding of God and creation, lead by an
easy path to the view that human beings fully realize themselves by
producing concepts that give us mastery over limitless
possibilities—first mastery over nature, then over ourselves.
Since modern thought develops within the nominalist frame, sculpted by
Ockham’s razor, it can only look upon the older tradition as a form of
inferior speculation that has been chastened and surpassed by more
methodical and rigorous thought. Fuller is supremely uncritical of this
perspective. He never pauses to consider how one might adjudicate the
controversy between Aquinas’s doctrine of analogy and Scotist univocity.
In this he is in good company. Even such a brilliant and subtle study
as The Theological Origins of Modernity, by Michael Gillespie,
simply assumes that nominalism attained victory over the older tradition
because of an intrinsic superiority. This presumption flatters the
complacency of the modern mind, and prevents us from seeing the poverty
of our current assumptions about reason, nature, and human fulfillment.
The
other great failure of Fuller’s account (also shared by Gillespie) is
his interpretation of the Christian tradition in terms of the dualism
of body and soul. Such dualism is the opposite of Christianity, a trick
of perspective fabricated during the Enlightenment, perfected by
Nietzsche, and generally widespread among educated Westerners today,
many of them Christian.
In Fuller’s interpretation, the
Judeo-Christian doctrine that we are made in the image of God means that
we have as-yet unrealized, godlike possibilities, and original sin
denotes the weakness and drag of our non-godlike bodies. On this
reading, Christianity mandates rebellion against our finitude through
efforts to rise spiritually above the failures of the body.
This,
in fact, is not Christian orthodoxy at all, but rather Gnosticism, one
of the great heresies. Augustine explicitly rejected Gnosticism in the
Manichean form he knew intimately. He understood original sin as the
disordered will to self-exaltation. Far from being a source of sin, our
embodied condition is pronounced good in the first chapter of Genesis.
Like Marcion, a Christian heretic excommunicated in the second century,
the Gnostics repudiated the depiction of God in the Hebrew Scriptures,
beginning with the affirmation in Genesis 1 that the whole creation of
earth and the heavens is good. According to Gnosticism, only pure spirit
is good; the body and the material world are evil and the source of all
evil. Gnostics wanted to purify and detach their spirits from material
existence by ascetic disciplines, including abstention from sex and
procreation. It was the culture of death calling itself Christianity.
The
dualism we find in Descartes encourages a modern form of Gnosticism.
The world is not an order of beings manifesting God’s goodness; it is
rather an order of inert matter in motion, available for the human will
and intellect to master and manipulate. Ancient Gnosticism sought
deliverance from evil by severing the spirit’s ties to the material
world. Modern Gnosticism appears at first to take a much more optimistic
view of creation. Its hopes, however, are not placed in nature as
created, but rather in the mind’s capacity to construct models that will
unlock the powers trapped within the given order of beings, so as to
release their infinite possibilities and make them subservient to our
needs and aspirations. It hopes to escape evil not by fleeing the world,
but by stepping away in distrust, securing the independent power of the
mind through the scientific method, and then turning against the world
with a vengeance and transforming it to suit the human will.
This
Gnostic attitude manifests itself in the economic realm. The
Lockean-Marxist doctrine of human labor holds that our work imparts
value to a natural world that is in itself mere raw material for the
will, worthless except insofar as it harbors productive potential to be
unleashed and exploited. Though he misnames it Christianity, Fuller
recognizes this Gnostic vision at the heart of his own
techno-libertarian stance. According to him, transhumanism looks upon
the natural human body as raw material, a platform from which we can
launch our possible selves. Securing solidarity and cooperation for this
agenda, however, requires extending reason’s mastery and control over
social relations of distribution as well, so as to ensure that the
possibilities of self-transcendence are widely shared by “humanity.”
Fuller’s advocacy of transhumanism has cultural resonance because he
articulates and celebrates the theological principles that structure and
orient modern thought. While his account is often sloppy, he is
nevertheless right that the transhumanist agenda is a logical
consequence of Gnosticism (which he and many others mistake for
Christianity), and that this Gnosticism, which has theological roots in
the Scotist-nominalist revolution in metaphysics, ever more exclusively
shapes the modern cultural imagination and our understanding of what it
is to be human. His failure to interpret correctly the philosophical
and theological traditions that precede this revolution shows how
difficult it is to think outside the nominalist and Gnostic horizon once
we’re inside it, especially when our technologically mediated
relationship to the natural world and our own bodies reinforces its hold
on us.
Fortunately, this
constricted modern horizon is a cave from which it is still possible to
escape. One way we can start is by recognizing that Fuller’s arithmetic
is faulty. Humanity already experienced decisive enhancements well
before the fourteenth century, expansions beyond the horizons within
which it had previously been confined. What Fuller is celebrating is not
Humanity 2.0, but rather Humanity 4.5.
In order to see the
history of humanity in the West more clearly, we need to turn on its
head a characteristic, self-congratulating modern description of the
philosophical achievement that Descartes is thought to have
accomplished. He is often said to have inaugurated the “subjective
turn”—credited with recognizing that we have to start from an analysis
of consciousness and treat all the “objects” of our knowledge as shaped,
distorted, conditioned by our “subjective” filters. By correcting for
the filter, we render knowledge more “objective.”
Much of modern
thought is devoted to rigorous methods of objectivity, accompanied by
ever-increasing critique of the ways in which our subjectivity
(individual and social) renders that objectivity difficult, if not
impossible. The scientific method is supposed to filter out the
subjective biases of the individual observer. Meanwhile, the “masters of
suspicion”—Marx, Nietzsche, Freud, and their followers—expose and
deconstruct the distorting ideologies, fantasies, and power-seeking
strategies to which we are inescapably prone.
Actual reflection
on the older tradition, however, makes clear that examination of the
human being as a knowing, doing, experiencing, and imagining subject has
never been missing, only differently pursued. The horizons of meaning
within which humans experience, reflect, question, imagine, and act have
certainly changed in different times and places, and thus the
understanding of what it means to be a “subject” has changed. But it
makes no sense to ask whether or not a particular historical era
presents us as subjects. The more revealing question is what we think we are subjects of.
Humanity 1.0.
The pre-philosophic pagan human being is the subject of powers, and
also subjected to powers. The polytheistic or animist world is one
swarming with conflicting powers, which occasionally bundle together
into unities that are never quite stable. The Babylonian god Marduk
violently imposing order on the monstrous brood of Tiamat (chaos)
provides one of the great symbols of Humanity 1.0. The pagan subject is a
temporary unity, able to channel and placate and enlist the powers of
this world for a time, until he eventually dissolves back into the all.
In Greece, the myth of Zeus overcoming his monstrous father Kronos by
means of intelligence and instituting the new order of the beautiful
Olympian gods encapsulates a particularly potent vision of pagan
subjectivity. The Sophists, who claimed to know how to make reason the
instrument of the concentration and command of power, exploited this
vision.
Humanity 2.0. This first expansion of
the horizon of the human comes about partly in response to the Sophists.
Starting with Socrates, ancient philosophers in the
Platonic-Aristotelian tradition contended that the human being is best
understood as the subject of wonder. Awakened by wonder, rational
inquiry opens us to a truth not ultimately grounded in power, but in the
Good. The subject of wonder is not simply a meeting point of
accumulated powers gathered at a center of control. On the contrary, he
is a subject that is always also oriented toward a center outside
itself. The wondering being is an “ecstatic” subject, from Greek ekstasis, standing outside oneself.
For Plato, we are preeminently erotic beings, in love with the
attractive beauty of goods and truths not of our own making. We are
penetrated and called forth by the intimate effects of beauty and truth,
drawn outside ourselves into the world and into contemplation. To
recognize that the world is a home for our contemplative understanding
and that this ecstatic existence fulfills our nature is to recognize the
goodness of the world. The world invites us to be transformed by its
truth, which satisfies our love.
As Fuller’s persistent
misreading of this tradition indicates, the impoverished modern horizon
cannot recognize or even understand that goodness is a principle of
being. Rather than an expansion of the human, the modern “subjective
turn” represents a refusal of ecstatic existence. It reinterprets our
erotic nature in individualist terms. In Walt Whitman’s image, the
modern subject is a solitary spider on a promontory, throwing forth
“filament, filament, filament, out of itself” in order to “explore the
vacant, vast surrounding.” Freud was able to introduce the erotic back
into a scientific discourse that had ceased to reflect upon it, making
the centrality of eros to human existence seem like a novel insight in
the early twentieth century. Yet he remained squarely within the modern
horizon, recasting the meaning of eros in terms of the modern isolated
subject.
Humanity 3.0.
Biblical culture opens a new horizon, proposing that the human being is
best understood as the subject of prayer. This, too, is an ecstatic
manner of being, summed up in Augustine’s Christian re-articulation of
Platonic eros: “Our heart is restless until it rests in Thee.” But as
Augustine indicates, the center in which we are re-centered outside
ourselves is the Creator whom we address as a person. In fact, this
Christian ecstatic mode of being brings with it the discovery of
personhood. The personhood of the Creator is manifested in his radically
free relationship to the created world, the radical freedom of agape,
the love that gives being. The pagan gods are not persons, but merely
participants in the ongoing contest of powers; Marduk does not
peacefully speak order into being, but violently imposes it on the
disorder that already exists. The god of the philosophers sustains the
orderliness of the world, but does not give it being in a free act of
love, and thus is not personal.
The Latin word persona (which translates the Greek prosopon) means a mask one wears, hence a role one plays, either theatrically or legally; it is not originally a kind of being that one is.
“Person” first becomes a category of being when applied to God in early
attempts to speak with some clarity about the mystery of the Trinity;
only thereafter is the human being in the image of God also considered a
person. The ground of this human personhood is the possibility of
communion with the person of the Creator by way of covenant and
sacrament, a possibility enacted and cultivated through prayer.
Because the world is given the gift of being, it is fundamentally good,
as God saw when he created it. God as Creator is other than the world,
not a part of it, but he is also fully and everywhere intimately present
to it and manifested by it. In communion of personhood with the
Creator, the Christian, raised and liberated by God’s grace, transcends
the world without ceasing to be part of it, still gratefully embedded
within the goodness of its created order of beings.
Humanity 3.5.
The tradition of Christian humanism, by joining together the dynamisms
of the previous two great expansions, arguably opens the maximal horizon
of human possibility. The biblical subject of prayer expands and
fulfills the classical philosophical subject of wonder. An ecstatic
existence in God allows for the amplification and clarification of an
ecstatic existence in the Good made possible by Humanity 2.0. This is
the horizon in which Aquinas, Dante, Thomas More, C. S. Lewis, Flannery
O’Connor, and the later Dostoyevsky explored the richness of human
existence.
Humanity 4.0.The
modern subject is perhaps best understood as the being who tries to
maintain the status of personhood and transcend the world, but without
relying upon ecstatic communion with the person of God. The options come
down to rejecting God entirely or reducing God to a useful projection
of human possibilities. In either case, the human is no longer an
ecstatic subject who receives the gift of being and the grace that
fructifies our nature, but is himself the primary source of
transcendence.
Since this transcendence no longer grounds itself ecstatically in the Creator of the world, it has to be attained by negation
of the world. So the “subjective turn” is a refusal of ecstatic
existence, a stepping back from the world, in preparation for its
domination by a now alien will and mind. The modern subject is thus the
subject of projects.
The subject of projects gives
modernity its Gnostic character. This world is not an inherently good
creation. A better alternative world remains to be made by us, in the
future. This alienated, negative, transformative stance toward the world
actively and habitually rejects the identification of being and
goodness.
Thus the horizon of modernity can be strictly defined as the
horizon within which the goodness of being is no longer intelligible.
This is the horizon within which Fuller’s intellectual history is
confined, from within which he champions modern science and
technological innovation as the great collective project of modernity.
Transcendence is defined as the reappropriation of the world from the
standpoint of the human capacity to be the subject of projects.
Humanity 4.5.
The distinctly transhumanist horizon comes about when our project of
mastery turns its attention to our own bodies. They come to be treated
as raw material, resources available to satisfy our free individual
preferences. Our will to transcend nature through projects of mastery
mounts a rebellion against the natural constraints of the organic human
body, harnessing the power of technological innovations to render it the
instrument of our arbitrary will. Why should we tolerate bondage to our
frail flesh when we can split atoms and destroy cities?
From the
low-tech mania for tattooing and piercing, through the medium-tech
tools of abortion, hormonal birth control, and transgendering, to the
high-tech visions and explorations of genetic engineering and cyborgism,
this rebellion seems to be gathering steam. An aggressive assertion of
bodily self-ownership is becoming the new normal, with the status of a
fundamental right.
Politically
speaking, the assertion of individual self-ownership is a central
feature of libertarianism. The transhumanism of Humanity 4.5 is thus an
extreme expression of the libertarianism that is spreading through
American society, increasingly bankrolling and driving the agenda of
both major political parties. Its animating principles are far from a
fringe phenomenon, however far-fetched its bio-technological fantasies
may sound.
Transhumanists, like other libertarians, make the
mistake of thinking that the high-spirited few, who are enamored of
ascetic self-overcoming and relentless power-accumulating work, will be
welcomed as the model and standard for the security-oriented many, who
prefer to live according to their appetites, and whose escape fantasy is
giant cruise ships rather than silicone bodies. To the extent that it
has not shed the heritage of Christian humanism, libertarianism imagines
itself as a redemptive project of liberation for all humanity, not just
the zealous few. But there is nothing egalitarian about a moral vision
that flows from understanding human dignity in terms of
transcendence-seeking projects; and libertarians, under the brutalizing
influence of Ayn Rand, seem to have become increasingly honest about the
inegalitarian consequences of their agenda.
Fuller resists this
tendency. He advances proposals for sharing the technological fruits of
the proactionary principle in a socialist manner. But they have no basis
in his understanding of what it is to be human and are thus likely to
fall away as unsupported by the logic of Humanity 4.5. His Promethean
agenda employs the same salesmanship so often used by Humanity 4.0.
Francis Bacon appropriated the word “charity” to brand his vision of
techno-mastery. Fuller likes to tell the story of “humanity” marching
through history and destined to prevail. This mythical protagonist masks
the reality that the powers we accumulate are always the powers of some
and not of others. A more realistic portrayal of the future of Humanity
4.5 would star the relative few who are going to use the enormous
wealth accumulated by the globalist bourgeois empire to fund their own
Promethean futures, self-cast in the role of “early adopters” whose job
is to keep the cutting edge of progress sharp. Meanwhile, the supporting
cast of millions will remain in pecuniary thrall, hoping for a better
role in the promised but not yet budgeted sequel.
There is no
shortage of contemporary mythmaking seeking to prop up confidence in the
idol of progress. The more the empire of economic, political, and
scientific mastery shows signs of imminent collapse (at least in the
West), the more the anxiety of control increases, generating an
increasingly desperate need to convince ourselves that progress is still
the ultimate truth about reality.
The
current wave of dystopian young adult fiction, for example, serves the
same kind of public liturgical function for progressive individualism as
the New Year liturgy of Marduk’s victory over Tiamat once did for a
strong Babylonian kingship. In these stories, disasters resulting from
technological or political threats generate a social order that fails to
deliver liberation of the individual. The adolescent heroes inevitably
find their true identities as they lead a political revolution to put
social progress back on track. Surely, the problem must be bad
technocrats trying to concentrate all the power and benefits in their
own hands! The solution, of course, lies in putting a more beneficent
management in place to spread the benefits equitably. The fantasy of
political revolution thus serves as therapy: It maintains faith in the
order of the universe under the reign of progress.
Fuller’s
proposals for risk management play the same reassuring, therapeutic, and
religious role, and are equally fantastical. He rightly accuses the
“precautionary principle” of lacking “faith in human power and
intelligence,” thereby revealing the true object of his own religious
faith. His “God” provides assurance that, in the harmony of the final
reckoning, all the harms done along the historical trajectory of
self-transcendence will be overbalanced by the enhancements. It should
come as no surprise that in his adolescence, Fuller was educated by
Jesuits in the heyday of their enthusiasm for the cosmic evolutionism of
Teilhard de Chardin. Nor should it be surprising if many find his
facile justification of the ways of God attractive. In the idolatry of
progress, the only sin is the refusal of optimism.
A sense of
urgency animates the proactionary imperative, and it engenders the most
ludicrous aspect of the transhumanist faith’s mythmaking. If progress
is inevitable, if we continue to make discoveries that deliver
enhancement and contribute to our self-overcoming, why do
transhumanists feel an almost desperate need to speed the pace of
discovery? From the vantage point of Humanity 3.5, the insistence on
faster solutions to human limitations seems a lot like an inability to
come to a mature reckoning with finitude and death. The translation of
the fantasies of transhumanists into policy proposals looks like
provision for a race of hysterical adolescents striking heroic poses as
they cling ever more tightly to their idols.
Fortunately,
it is still possible, despite the march of humanity through history, to
see the human person from the vantage point of Humanity 3.5. The
transcendent dignity of the human person in communion with the Creator
is still capable of speaking to our depths—the more so to the extent
that the fantastical mythology of “H+” is exposed as fraudulent and
cleared out of the way, allowing us to notice that we have depths to
speak to. This possibility seems to account for a significant but seldom
noted social phenomenon. As techno-liberation has become more
aggressive, and the cultural swindle of its humanistic façade more
apparent, the American genius of voluntary association has produced a
response. The steady growth of classical academies and classical
Christian homeschooling seems to testify to a growing realization that
the classical Christian humanism of Humanity 3.5 is the real liberation
of humanity and cultivation of human dignity.
A spontaneous
renewal of humane culture will, of course, face considerable opposition
as the idolaters of progress recognize the full scope of its
nonconformity. We need to protect the growth of these precious seeds in a
number of ways. First and foremost are legal safeguards for the right
to educate. Second, biblically inspired institutions of higher education
need increasing self-awareness that the vision of humanity, nature, and
God that provides their identity has to be defended in its integrity.
Third, in both classical schooling and higher education, a
self-conscious recovery of a biblical and philosophical understanding of
created nature and the practical and spiritual relationship to it that
fosters the human good must have a place in the curriculum. Metaphysical
reflection and the cultivation of wonder provide the indispensable
foundation for a critique of and response to the Gnostic culture that
dominates our lives.
The machinery we have constructed to
exercise control has a way of exercising control over us. The image of
the “singularity,” the point at which artificial and human intelligence
merge, haunts our cultural imagination. The real threat, however, is
that our new possibilities become new needs, and our enhancements define
a new normal that we can’t bear to fall short of. The idol of progress
is as fertile in the demand for human sacrifices as any Baal of the
past, whether in the form of self-mutilations, throwing our children
into the fire of competitive frenzy to become productive functionaries
of the exploitative machinery of power, or the insidious spread of the
despairing and sometimes suicidal sense that we are mere spiders wearied
by throwing out filaments that never attach to anything solid. Only
recovering ampler horizons of truth about God, humanity, and the
goodness of creation can set us free and renew a culture of life and
love.
Mark Shiffman is associate professor of classical studies at Villanova University.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Comments are subject to deletion if they are not germane. I have no problem with a bit of colourful language, but blasphemy or depraved profanity will not be allowed. Attacks on the Catholic Faith will not be tolerated. Comments will be deleted that are republican (Yanks! Note the lower case 'r'!), attacks on the legitimacy of Pope Francis as the Vicar of Christ (I know he's a material heretic and a Protector of Perverts, and I definitely want him gone yesterday! However, he is Pope, and I pray for him every day.), the legitimacy of the House of Windsor or of the claims of the Elder Line of the House of France, or attacks on the legitimacy of any of the currently ruling Houses of Europe.