From Medium
By Jonathan Culbreath
“Integralism”
is a word that has, slowly but surely, been crawling to the surface of
political discourse on media platforms recently, as conservatives have
begun to engage in heated debate about the merits of adherence to the
axioms of classical liberalism. Conservatism in America has long been
characterized — even before the fusionism of the Reagan era — by a firm
appreciation of the principles of Enlightenment liberalism, especially
as they are enshrined in the glorious founding documents of the United
States of America. Among these principles is the sovereignty of the
individual human being and his rights, which are his by nature, simply
on account of who he is — and they are inalienable. The role of
government, claims the old liberal — and claims the Constitution — is
nothing other than to protect these inalienable rights from the
interference of others, and to abstain from interfering in them itself,
unless it is absolutely necessary to do so in order to maintain a
maximal degree of pluralistic equality among men. This is liberalism —
and it is also well-known as American conservatism.
In a recent article,
which as attracted much controversy, socially conservative Catholic
author, Sohrab Ahmari, has attacked what he calls “David Frenchism” —
essentially the above form of liberalism — for failing to be a
formiddable oponent of left-wing progressivism, which threatens to
undermine socially conservative, and especially Christian, ethical and
religious values. A classical liberal by all accounts, David French
believes:
that the institutions of a technocratic market society are neutral zones that should, in theory, accommodate both traditional Christianity and the libertine ways and paganized ideology of the other side. Even if the latter — that is, the libertine and the pagan — predominate in elite institutions, French figures, then at least the former, traditional Christians, should be granted spaces in which to practice and preach what they sincerely believe.
With
remarkable clarity and brevity, Ahmari demonstrates why the logic of
this political pluralism, justifiable only on the basis of adherence to
the classical liberal principles expressed in the American founding
documents, inevitably leads away from the socially
conservative ethical values which French, and many other
conservative-liberals like him, hold dear. To adhere to political
liberalism while maintaining one’s social conservatism is to fight an
uphill battle.
In stark contrast, Ahmari himself envisions no other way to engage in political discourse than “to
fight the culture war with the aim of defeating the enemy and enjoying
the spoils in the form of a public square re-ordered to the common good
and ultimately the Highest Good.” This is a political vision that honestly and openly takes a stance, and
makes a point of implementing it politically. No pretenses about the
“priority of culture” can ever hope to lead a society to virtue, as
conceived by social conservatives. On the contrary, this can only be
done by a combative engagement with the art of politics and a
utilization of the coercive state towards the common good.
Other voices in the media, such as Ross Douthat of The New York Times, have explicitly connected this line of thinking to “integralism,” which has been defined at The Josias as
a “a tradition of thought that rejects the liberal separation of
politics from concern with the end of human life, holding that political
rule must order man to his final goal.” While neither Douthat nor
Ahmari would be happy to identify as integralists, a question that is
beginning to arise is whether there is any other coherent political
philosophy — or theology — that has proposed anything like a positive
alternative to political liberalism, whether of the classical or
progressive variety (they are, after all, connected).
The
assertive post-liberal politics that both authors are proposing has
likewise been called for — with even greater vim and vigour — by known
integralists such as Gladden Pappin and Adrian Vermeule, in the increasingly renowned post-liberal American Affairs journal. Vermeule has gone so far as to claim — and in this, it seems to me, Ahmari agrees with him — that progressive liberalism
has moved beyond classical “conservative” liberalism, and now seeks
openly to engage with substantive questions of truth and the formation
of strong political identities. (Classical conservative liberalism, to
be clear, does not abstain from thus engaging in questions of truth; it
only refuses to admit that it does so.) Liberalism, claims Vermeule,
even sets itself up as its own religion, with its own sacraments, its
own liturgies, its own theology — at least in some vague sense. The
proportionate response to such a politics is decidedly not to
take a stance of supposed neutrality. To do so is in fact not to be
genuinely neutral, but to become politically weak and defenseless, to
render oneself vulnerable to the onslaught of whatever political
ideology happens to reign. The proper response can only be to invoke an
assertive political vision that is equal to, or greater than, but
opposite to the political theology of liberalism. For Vermeule, the
natural choice is the political theology of the Catholic faith, or what
is known as integralism.
Integralism
begins with the first premise that it is the role of politics to direct
human beings to their final end, the purpose for which they were
created by God, their highest good — which is of course God himself. The
end or purpose of human life is union with God, and political power
directs humans to this end. But this end has two distinct but
interrelated dimensions: a temporal dimension and an eternal dimension,
or a natural and a supernatural dimension. To these two dimensions of
the end, or the good, there correspond two
dimensions of political power itself: a temporal power and and a
spiritual power, or the State and the Church. These institutions have
distinct but interrelated jurisdictions over matters directed to the two
dimensions of the good. Consequently, they are
obligated to cooperate towards the joint attainment of this end, in its
two dimensions. It is obvious at this point that integralism is
diametrically opposed to the classic liberal principle of the separation
of Church and State, expressed in the First Amendment to the
Constitution — which is just one application of the general liberal
commitment to political neutrality. Integralism, unlike classical
liberalism, adheres to an assertive and substantive vision of the
political good, making no pretenses of a politics which abstains from
such a vision.
Such a politics is no doubt alien and unbelievable from a classically liberal standpoint — even from the standpoint of many Catholics who
adhere to conservative liberal fusionism. To these Catholics and
conservatives, it is unthinkable and unrealistic to hope that politics
could ever assume a positively religious quality. Integralism appears as
nothing but a nostalgic and utopian ideology, akin to Fascism or
Marxism. But the direction of current political discourse seems to
indicate that conservative liberal fusionism itself is not only failing as a political strategy, but that the only posture that anybody can
realistically take in politics is one that is explicitly religious and
theological, as Vermeule so convincingly argues about progressivism
itself. Progressivism, the natural child of liberalism, is also somehow
at odds with the older tenets of classical liberalism, being the
manifestation of the inherent instabilities of any liberalism which
claims to be politically neutral. Progressivism is the proof that no
political philosophy can properly function if it does not forthrightly
embrace a political theology. In this conviction,
progressivism has the right instinct; only, the particular theology
which it embraces is an idolatrous one. But idolatry, as the ancient
fathers of Christianity knew, is the inevitable outcome of lukewarmness —
which is not a neutral disposition by any means, but positively
vicious; and liberalism was always lukewarm to begin with. The only
alternative can be to embrace a theology which is neither vicious nor
idolatrous, but truly virtuous and ordained to the worship of a true
God.
Conservatives
— and especially Catholics who should know better — must acknowledge
that they cannot engage in meaningful politics if they do not also
engage in some form of political theology. The failure to acknowledge
this does not amount to an abstinence from so engaging, but only a
failure to do so honestly and reflexively — which is to do theology
badly. To be sure, one who begins to engage in a meaningful and
productive way with some form of political theology might not get so far
as integralism or Catholic social doctrine per se; one
might only get as far as formulating a vague idea of the relevance of
the Christian religion for politics. This can be formulated with varying
degrees of clarity, in thinkers who honestly engage with questions of
these sorts.
Thinkers such as Sohrab Ahmari and Ross Douthat, as well as the now famous author of Why Liberalism Failed, Patrick
Deneen, are only just beginning to formulate this idea of a politics
ordered to a substantive vision of the common good. Not yet having
engaged in political theology as such, these thinkers are motivated by a
conception of the common good which is nonetheless partially
theological, insofar as it relies on an ancient philosophical tradition
of treatment with the idea of God. But it remains properly
philosophical, even if it is distantly motivated by something resembling
theology. Consequently, Ahmari and Douthat are both resistant to
integralism, even as they are pushed to pursue a politics more
explicitly aimed at the common good.
A more erudite political philosophy sharing the same motivations is expressed in the prolific work of Alasdaire Macintyre,
one of the most renowned moral thinkers still living, who was
post-liberal “before it was cool.” Macintyre famously advocates for a
politics of the common good that transgresses the boundaries and
limitations of conventional left-right liberalism. Moral discourse in
America, remarks Macintyre, is marked by a refusal to engage in
conscious thought regarding the end and purpose of
human life. The recovery of such a consideration, on the basis of
traditional Aristotelian and Thomistic philosophy, is the hallmark of
Macintyre’s ethical and political thought.
But not even Macintyre has made it completely to integralism. Indeed, the mark of all of these post-liberal thinkers is that have not adequately engaged with the properly theological political
doctrine of the Catholic Church of which they all are members, even as
this doctrine remotely guides their explorations in political
philosophy. Students of traditional Catholic theology know that, among
the many sub-divisions of theology, the category whose subject matter
covers the political institution of the Church is ecclesiology. In
ecclesiology, the theologian studies everything that the Church teaches
regarding her role as a universal (catholic) society instituted by
Christ for the salvation of all men — a common good. The Church is in
this way the political institution par excellence. If her ecclesiology is true, then all men who seek the truth are obliged to submit to her authority as the most universal political (or meta-political,
given her supernatural character) institution. Furthermore, if her
ecclesiology — her political theology — is true, then any politics which honestly engages with the theological dimensions of its commitments must eventually embrace integralism.
The
embrace of integralism, and the subordination of states to the sole
universal jurisdiction of the Catholic Church, is the solution to all of
the problems which are facing liberals — and conservatives — not only
in America, but globally. Under the jurisdiction of the Church, no
government can pretend to uphold religious neutrality, a pretense that
has only proven destructive to truly religious customs, conservative
mores, and human happiness in general. The enshrinement of individual
liberty as the god of liberalism has only allowed the powerful to
oppress the weak, in order to appease their own self-interest.
Communities have broken down; people no longer share and participate
with one another in meaningful activity, culture, or worship; the rich
grow richer while the poor grow poorer; children are misled by perverse
sexual ideologies taught to them in their classrooms; the unborn are
daily sacrificed to the idol of American liberty. Any quasi-libertarian
embrace of political neutrality and tolerant pluralism is simply
counterproductive, especially from the perspective of Catholics and
social conservatives. The only legitimately productive political action
is to take a stance in the face of aggressive opposition, and eventually
to capture the very political apparatuses which presently support a
system of oppression and convert them into a servant of the Catholic
Church.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Comments are subject to deletion if they are not germane. I have no problem with a bit of colourful language, but blasphemy or depraved profanity will not be allowed. Attacks on the Catholic Faith will not be tolerated. Comments will be deleted that are republican (Yanks! Note the lower case 'r'!), attacks on the legitimacy of Pope Francis as the Vicar of Christ (I know he's a material heretic and a Protector of Perverts, and I definitely want him gone yesterday! However, he is Pope, and I pray for him every day.), the legitimacy of the House of Windsor or of the claims of the Elder Line of the House of France, or attacks on the legitimacy of any of the currently ruling Houses of Europe.